What is Truth?

Watch the full video here.

If I had to name the single most frustrating aspect of modern, popular debate, it would have to be the openly adversarial nature on which it all appears to operate. Rather than work together on building a better understanding of our world, we instead seem to be more focused on scoring philosophical points against the "opposition." Often times, this might even be by design, like in a courtroom setting where both advocates must dogmatically argue on behalf of their clients’ best interests. The rest of the time, however, it seems to just happen spontaneously---as if no one really knows what the rules are when engaging in this process. That's why so much philosophical debate in this world feels a lot like trying to play a game of chess against an opponent who thinks that this is supposed to be checkers. Without some formal agreement over what truth is and how to recognize the truth when we see it, then there is simply no way to productively engage with opposing points of view.
 
To me, this presents a very strong incentive to just sit down and summarily examine the question of "What is truth?" Fortunately, in the context of philosophical and mathematical logic, there are actually very well-established answers to this question. It's just that you wouldn't really know it because no one ever seems capable of spelling them all out within a single, comprehensive reference. That’s why I feel personally motivated to present my findings on this issue. It’s a perfect opportunity to explicitly lay the foundations of basic epistemology for everyone to see, such that we can finally begin to hold each other accountable to a more rigorous set of philosophical rules.
 
To begin, it's important to understand that any time we talk about a thing like truth, we're not talking about some intrinsic metaphysical quality of reality itself. Technically, what we're really talking about is a property of propositions. That is to say, propositions can either be true or they can be false, but there is no such thing as raw "essence of truth" interwoven into the fabric of space and time.  Speaking more formally, a truth value is classically defined as a member of a binary set that contains the elements "True" and "False"  [1]. The purpose of this set is to serve as a kind of marker for linguistic propositions in order to help us measure their epistemic "correctness." What exactly that means is open to some interpretation, but we can give it a rigorous definition through a mechanism known as a truth assignment. Speaking formally again, a truth assignment (also called a truth valuation, or an interpretation) is defined as a mapping function between the set of simple linguistic propositions and the set of binary truth values.
 
If that sounds a bit technical at first, then just think of it like this: Imagine me writing down a simple proposition on a post-it note and placing it in front of you. In your left hand is a giant rubber stamp that says "true" while in your right hand is a another giant rubber stamp that says "false." Your job is to decide which label deserves to be stamped on this note. So ask yourself, how do you go about doing that? Do you just arbitrarily stamp things randomly? Or do you apply some set of rules that give your labels a more significant meaning? Whatever answer you give to this question is effectively your truth assignment function. It's an algorithm that takes simple linguistic propositions as an input and then determines a binary truth value as the output.
 
Now let's take it one step further. Suppose you've stamped a dozen or so of these post-it notes with truth values, when suddenly you feel like connecting them together into more complex arrangements. For example, maybe you think two true propositions connected left to right should also be stamped with a value of "true."  Or maybe you think two false propositions connected top to bottom should always be "false." Maybe you think propositions stamped with "true" on the top should all be stamped with "false" on the bottom, and vice-versa.  These are all perfectly valid operations, and represent the role of logical connectives contained within the scope of propositional logic. We like using logical connectives because they allow us to literally "connect" propositions together, thereby creating more interesting propositional formulas.

Notice also how there's nothing physically forcing us to stick with only a binary set of truth values. For example, maybe you think truth would make more sense if we used a ternary set of values rather than binary.  It's a perfectly valid conception that's even used in practice today by scientists, engineers, and mathematicians [2]. Some systems of logic even treat truth as a continuum value rather than a discrete set [3], and again find use in modern scientific applications. There is no objectively right or wrong answer except for the collective say-so of human philosophers in our ultimate quest for a meaningful conception of truth. 

This is all pretty standard material so far, and can readily be verified in most relevant textbooks on the subject [4,5]. However, something you generally won't find is an official stance over the precise nature of an ideal truth assignment.  It's as if we're all experts at manipulating truth values once we have them, but no one knows how to go about assigning those actual truth values in the first place. That's a real shame, because this question represents the heart of what an idea like truth is supposed to philosophically encapsulate. At best, we only seem to have this vague notion that truth should, in some way or another, represent a kind of "correspondence" between the set of linguistic propositions and the factual state of affairs in objective reality. True propositions are those which effectively describe the real world as it really is, while false propositions do not.

This is a fairly common epistemic concept that philosophers like to call the correspondence theory of truth. And, at first glance, it does seem to be a pretty intuitive definition. Unfortunately, there's also a glaring hole that needs to be addressed. Namely, what exactly is this "correspondence" thing you speak of, and how do I recognize it when I see it?  For example, consider a simple proposition like "the Moon is round." Is that true or false? According to correspondence theory, the best we can say is that if the Moon is round, then it is "true" that the Moon is round.  Since that's obviously just a vapid tautology, correspondence theory of truth hasn't really told me anything about how to assign truth to propositions. 

But let's take it even further.  What if I stand outside one evening and simply look at the moon directly with my own eyes?  That way, if I see a generally roundish object, then I can legitimately say that the Moon is round, right?

Well, no.

For example, what if there was some kind of optical illusion brought on by the atmosphere that makes squareish things appear round? Or what if I'm just looking at a giant photograph of the moon, or maybe some elaborate hologram?  Maybe it's all just an hallucination brought on by drugs, or perhaps a really vivid, lucid dream. Maybe I'm being tricked by a magical demon, or maybe I'm really just a brain in a vat, plugged into some kind of matrix simulation. I simply do not know, and what's more, I can't know. No amount of reason or evidence can ever allow me to perfectly determine objective reality as it really is. Correspondence theory of truth is therefore useless because it offers no way to differentiate between all of these competing  scenarios. So if we're ever going to make any progress in building a viable epistemology, then we need to operate under the basic constraints that nature has given us.

This is a fundamental philosophical concept known as the egocentric position, or equivalently, the problem of external world skepticism. All it says is that for whatever sensory perception you may be experiencing at any given moment, there are limitless ad hoc explanations for what might be causing it. Remember that I'm just a sentient agent trapped within my immediate mental awareness. It's not like I can just crawl out of that awareness and directly perceive reality as it really is. And even if I could, how exactly would I correspond linguistic propositions to those objective states? What are the rules I have to follow and how do I apply them? We simply cannot ignore the fundamental barriers that exist between reality, our perceptions of reality, and our linguistic frameworks for describing reality.

This is the part where many philosophers really begin to butt heads with each other, but there are at least a few general principles that most people do tend to agree on. For example, one theory of truth that has great utility is known as the principle of mental incorrigibility, or simply empiricism. All this says is that any honest statement of immediate sensory perception is automatically a true proposition.  For example, consider a statement like "I feel a pain in my foot". Even if it turns out to be a complete illusion (like an amputee with a bad case of phantom limb syndrome) I still cannot deny the fact that I am definitely experiencing a distinct sensory perception that is unique from many others. It therefore seems perfectly reasonable to just acknowledge our perceptual data for what it is, designate those experiences with linguistic markers, and then assign a basic truth value to such propositions accordingly. 

Another popular method for assigning truth to propositions is the use of axiomatic formalism, or for the sake of this discussion, rationalism. Basically, all this system says is that certain "obvious" propositions, called axioms, deserve a specific truth-value by rote fiat.  For example, take the reflexive law of equality: A = A. No one derived this proposition from any prior logical framework, nor was it empirically discovered hiding under some rock. It was just asserted outright as "true" because mathematicians needed a concept of equality from which to build a working system of algebra.  

Once we finally settle on an agreeable set of axioms, it then becomes possible to generate new true propositions out of the old ones by exercising rules of inference. For example, one classic rule of inference is the transitive law of equality: if A=B and B=C, then A=C. Again, no one derived this rule from any deeper foundations, nor was it empirically discovered. It was just asserted outright as a thing we're allowed to do with the concept of numerical equality.  Any new propositions generated in such a fashion are then called theorems, and they represent the core driver behind all propositional and mathematical logic.

This might feel like strangely circular reasoning at first glance, and in all fairness, it kind of is. However, contrary to popular misconceptions, axiomatic systems like math and logic make no effort to describe any objective sense of mind-independent reality. Rather, a far better way to think of such systems is as a kind of highly formalized language. Good axiomatic assertions are therefore not really circular so much as they are definitional. That's why all logical and mathematical theorems are said to analytic in nature, because such truths are ultimately derived entirely from the raw meaning we impose on the terms themselves, and not from any direct connection they have to the external world.  One could even argue that this makes analytic propositions a kind of formal extension on the incorrigible, since anyone is internally free to define their own personal vocabulary however they like.

But what about the so-called synthetic propositions that actually do attempt to describe objective reality---that is to say, the world "out there" beyond purely mental processes?  For example, consider a proposition like "all bachelors are bald" or maybe "all dogs live on Earth." How do I assign truth to propositions in this category? Again, it's not like I can just pop open a can of reality and directly observe the facts of the matter beyond my senses. Nor can I logically derive their truth from any assigned meaning to the words themselves.  So what do we do?

This is another point where things tend to get very confusing, simply because there are so many oddball truth assignments to choose from and no real official answers to turn to. For example, suppose we decide to assign truth to propositions that reinforce our sense of personal identity or social status. Let's call this egotistical validation. Granted, it might not be a very good system, but it's still a perfectly valid function that operates under well-defined rules. Maybe you've even encountered this system yourself, like in religious or political discussions where personal emotions tend to run very high.
 
Another interesting class of synthetic truth assignment is called Biblical inerrancy, and simply says that no true proposition can ever contradict the records contained within the Holy Bible. It's actually a fairly common truth assignment, typically emerging from religious fundamentalist organizations.  Truth, in their view, is basically whatever the Bible says. So while it is tempting to criticize the implicit goals contained within such a definition, it is hard to ignore the clear, meaningful distinction it represents.
 
But let's face facts. Those truth assignments are obviously arbitrary and completely unsatisfying because they make no effort to philosophically connect our beliefs with any objective sense of mind-independent reality. Unless we can find a way to overcome the egocentric position imposed on us by nature, then no system of truth assignment will ever have any meaningful sense of merit. That’s why so much of the philosophical debate in our world appears to be so pointless. Most truth assignment functions utilized in practice are either needlessly arbitrary, brazenly self-serving, or deliberately obtuse.
 
To address this problem, I find that it helps to step back and ask ourselves a fundamental question about truth that surprisingly few philosophers ever seem to ask. Namely, why is it so god-damned important to believe in as many "true" propositions as possible while simultaneously rejecting as many of the "false?" What difference does it make at the end of the day?  For instance, consider a possible world where everything I believe about the universe just so happens to be categorically false. However, every single time I make a decision based off of those beliefs, the consequences are maximally predictable and desirable for me anyway. Likewise, any time I commit a single "true" belief to action, the outcome is never predictable or desirable for me at all. Now let’s ask ourselves - given such a world, is it even meaningful to call any of my beliefs "false?”  And if so, why would I ever want to believe anything that was true? I could spend my entire life being completely wrong about absolutely everything and actually be better off for it. 
 
This simple thought experiment represents the core principle behind a system of truth assignment generally known as pragmatism. All this system has to say is that the only meaningful reason why anyone would ever bother believing anything at all is so that we can eventually use that information as a guide for our actions. Decisions based on “true” beliefs will therefore manifest themselves in the form of controlled, predictable experiences, while decisions based on “false” beliefs will eventually fail in that goal. Any beliefs that refuse to drive any actions whatsoever, even in principle, are thus effectively reduced to useless rhetorical gibberish.

To illustrate how this system might work in practice, simply imagine yourself standing at a busy intersection when suddenly you decide that you'd like to walk across to the other side. Sure, you can axiomatically declare premises and logically deduce conclusions all you want, but sooner or later you're going to have to translate that information into a real, committed action. So while you may think you're being very clever with all your intellectual presumptions and sophisticated rhetoric, I have yet to encounter a single philosopher who could successfully argue with a speeding bus. Everyone, everywhere, is therefore universally bound to the same pragmatic process in our daily epistemology.  We collect empirical data, we formulate it as a rationally descriptive model of objective reality, we exercise a decision accordingly, and then we empirically observe the outcome. If our understanding of traffic behavior is indeed "true," then we can expect to safely cross the street without incident. However, if our model contains flaws or inconsistencies, then it's only a matter of time before we eventually find ourselves getting plowed by oncoming traffic. 
This is what makes pragmatism the only epistemology with any viable sense of “connection” to the external world beyond our senses. Because even if my entire reality is little more than a glorified matrix simulation or demon-spawned hallucination, then even that reality is still objectively real, and apparently operating in accordance with causally predictive patterns. So if on the off-chance that my actions have any influence on the outcome of future events, then I can use those outcomes to gain real information about the rules governing my reality. Beliefs drive actions, actions have consequences, and consequences are objective. 
We can give this process a nice, technical-sounding name like pragmatic empirical rationalism, but really, it's all just a glorified way of saying science. Because really, that's all science fundamentally boils down to; a formalized system of gathering empirical data, expressing it within a rational, predictive framework, and then testing those predictions against quantifiable actions and consequences. We like basing our beliefs on scientific methods because it ultimately allows us to make real decisions in the real world with real, empirical consequences. Mental incorrigibility and axiomatic formalism are not mere ends unto themselves, but essential tools for the greater purpose of pragmatically navigating the world.
Notice also how the pragmatic framework implicitly captures many other familiar principles of both science and scientific method.  For example, consider the principle of fallibilism, which simply states that no synthetic propositional model can ever be assigned a value of "true" with any kind of perfect, universal certainty.  At best, we only know what to expect from such models if and when we ever happen to find them.  Consequently, all knowledge claims about objective reality must always remain open to possible revision when faced with any newer and better information.  Likewise, the principle of falsifiability states that we can indeed be perfectly confident in assigning certain models a value of false.  That's because the very definition of a false propositional model is one whose empirical predictions fail to come to pass.  Likewise, we can even use pragmatism to quantify the principle of Occam's Razor (also known as the principle of parsimony): given two propositional models that happen to make perfectly equivalent predictions, then the model containing fewer assumptions is automatically preferable.  After all, if both models are empirically equivalent either way, then you might as well just go with the one that takes less work to think about.
But hey, maybe that's being too presumptuous. Maybe you think pragmatism is a terrible principle of truth assignment, and that we should all replace it with some "higher" form of understanding.  But let's be clear about what that entails.Without some ultimately pragmatic purpose by which to measure our beliefs, then they are effectively disconnected from any empirically predictive decision we could ever hope to make. I could therefore openly concede every last proposition you have to say about reality, and literally nothing in my life would ever have change as a result.That's why no one cares how many angels can dance on the head of pin.  Any answer we give is necessarily going to be trivial and vacuous. We do, however, care a great deal about what medicines work best for treating cancer and why.  That's because any decisions we might hope to make on the subject are necessarily dependent on the final answers we give.  So unless your truth assignment can somehow facilitate my desire to solve actual problems and reliably predict the outcomes of my actions, then by definition and admission, it is irrelevant and worthless. Pragmatic scientific method therefore is the ultimate measure of all philosophical truth. 
Notes/References:
  1. Usually denoted as {T, F}.
  2. See tri-state logic
  3. See fuzzy logic
  4. Hodel, R. E, "An Introduction to Mathematical Logic," Dover Books (2013)
  5. Priest, G. "An Introduction to Non-classical Logic," 2nd Ed, Cambridge University Press (2008)

Existence by Definition: The Modal Ontological Argument Examined


The following is a philosophical analysis of the video essay, "The Ontological Argument." Video content is highlighted in red.
 
[0:00—0:27] In the year 1078, a monk named Anselm of Canterbury astonished the world by arguing that if it is even possible that God exists, then it follows logically that God does exist. Anselm’s argument came to be called the Ontological Argument, and it has sharply divided philosophers ever since.

If I had to name the single worst argument in the history of Christian philosophy, it would probably have to be the modal ontological argument for the existence of God. Not because it's a bad argument per se, but because of how aggressively bad it is. It's an argument that practically insults you with its own arrogance, and I find it genuinely baffling how Christian apologists try to defend this thing.

Imagine a hypothetical community of PhD scholars have been toiling for years on the ultimate argument for God's existence. Allegedly, this community is comprised skilled professionals who have devoted their lives to administering the Word of God and bringing souls unto salvation. Finally, the time comes to reveal their masterpiece of philosophical brilliance. This is the result:
 
"God exists because I say so, and if you don't like it, then you're just a stupid dummy head who eats babies."
 
Ask yourself right now. If you were a true-believing Christian, how exactly would this make you feel? How would it feel to know that your best and brightest minds were getting paid actual money to go on television and defend your God with this level of scholarship? 

Well, I don't know about you, but if I were a Christian, then I would be outraged. I would make it my personal business to ensure that all good Christians deny the blasphemous heretics who insulted my God with this level of prideful arrogance. So when the team at Reasonable Faith are basically doing exactly that with the ontological argument, I can't help but get confused. Most ordinary Christians seem to have the exact opposite reaction. They actually feel impressed with this thing, as if it were the greatest achievement in the philosophy of religion.
 
If that sounds a bit hyperbolic to you, then just listen to what this argument is supposedly saying:

  1. It is possible that God exists.
  2. Therefore, it is actual that God exists(?).

Ask yourself right now, how exactly is the mere possibility of anything supposed to logically entail its own existence? That has never been a thing in the history of math, science, or philosophy. It's as if the argument hasn’t even begun yet, and we can already tell that it is nothing but a giant failure waiting to happen.
 
It's important to understand that when we say it is possible for God to exist, we’re saying exactly that. It is possible. As in, maybe God exists, or maybe God doesn't exist. We don't know yet. At best, all we can establish is that the mere proposition itself---God exists---has at least one self-consistent interpretation. Yet according to Christian apologists, this simple fact, in an of itself, somehow supposed to logically entail God's real existence in the real world. 

I'm very sorry, guys, but that's just not how the world works, and you don't need a PhD in philosophy to understand why.

But who knows? Maybe I'm just being harsh. Maybe the ontological argument really is a triumph of Christian philosophy. William Lane Craig certainly seems to think so, and he even convinced a team of Reasonable Faith animators to put together an entire video about it. So by all means, guys. Take it away.

[0:27—0:42] The 19th century German philosopher Arthur Schopenhauer called it a “charming joke,” but many prominent 20th century philosophers, like Charles Hartshorne, Norman Malcolm, and Alvin Plantinga, think that it’s sound.

 

Okay, let’s just talk about this for a minute. There is a lot of subtle manipulation going on here, and I think it deserves to be recognized for what it is.

First off, take a look at this image and think about the message it seems to convey. On the right, I can clearly see three examples of "prominent 20th century philosophers" who think the ontological argument sound. In contrast, I'm only shown one example of a 19th century philosopher on the left, and apparently he dismissed it as a "joke." Furthermore, the guys on the right are clearly painted in red, while the guy on the left is painted blue—a color palate that just-so happens to correspond with right-wing conservatism and left wing liberalism. The obvious subtext therefore seems to be pretty obvious. The ontological argument is a highly sophisticated piece of good conservative deduction, and it is only an arrogant liberal minority that finds it objectionable.
This kind of thing really bothers me because on some fundamental level, they have to be doing it on purpose. It's so wildly misleading, too, that I can't help but question the integrity of those doing it. For starters, the overwhelming majority of modern professional philosophers are atheists [1]. That means, by definition, the majority of PhD-wielding philosophers---you know, the people who supposedly analyze this stuff for a living---are unconvinced by the ontological argument. Not only that, but it is generally understood that most theistic philosophers are unimpressed by it as well [2]. That means, for all practical purposes, the ontological argument is broadly considered to be a complete failure. Defenders of this argument are very much a minority within mainstream academic philosophy.
 
Now take a look at these supposed champions of the ontological argument. The video very clearly says that "prominent philosophers" think it is sound. Yet Charles Hartshorne and Norman Malcolm are basically nobodies [3]. Their contributions to philosophy are minuscule at best, and even dedicated students of philosophy have likely never heard of them. As far as I’m aware, Alvin Plantinga seems to be the only recognizable name in the bunch, but even he is widely regarded as a total crackpot. We’re seriously talking about a guy who wrote a 90-page essay in defense of the proposition that [4]:
 
“It is entirely right, rational, reasonable, and proper to believe in God without any evidence or argument at all.”
 
I'm sorry, guys, but these are not exactly intellectual heavyweights. If these really are the best examples of "prominent philosophers" you can gather, then what exactly does that say about the professional quality of your argument? It’s almost as if the production team at Reasonable Faith is counting on the fact that you've never really heard of these guys and that you'll just take their word for it that these supposedly "prominent" philosophers are held in high regard. 
 
Bear in mind now that I'm not saying any of this to debunk the ontological argument just yet. After all, ad hominen attacks are meaningless in philosophy, and we don't settle debates by appealing to authority. All I'm saying is that if you're going to contextualize the argument before presenting it, then the least you can do is be honest about it. And if you can't be honest about it, then what exactly does that say about the quality of your arguments? The ontological argument is not well respected among mainstream academic philosophers, and it is dishonest to give viewers any impression to the contrary.

Here it is: God can be defined as a maximally great being. If something were greater than God, then that being would be God. And in order to be maximally great, a maximally great being would have to be all powerful, all knowing, and morally perfect, in every possible world.

And there you have it, folks. The glorious ontological argument in a nutshell. God exists by pure, freaking definition. They don’t even try to hide it, either. It's all right there in black and white:

Step 1: Define the word “God" such that God as a maximally great being.  
Step 2: Define maximal greatness such that a maximally great being exists in all possible worlds.
Step 3: Define the actual world as a subset all possible worlds.
Step 4: Conclusion, therefore, God exists in actual world.
 
Can you see now why professional philosophers might describe this argument as “a charming joke?” It’s a textbook example of the classic logical fallacy known as begging the question. The argument just flat-out assumed its own conclusion by rote definition, and Christian apologists actually expect us to be impressed. So please allow me to make this perfectly clear, just in case there is any confusion.
 
When you define a word like "God," you are not generating information about the world. Rather, you are telling us about yourself. It's a declaration that, if and when you should ever happen to encounter the empirical manifestation of a particular set of properties, then you shall refer to that manifestation of properties as "God." However, it is an entirely separate matter as to where or not such entities actually exist somewhere to generate those manifestations in the first place. That is a matter of empirical investigation. It is therefore not logically possible for this argument to do what it claims.

[0:42—1:03] Possible worlds are simply ways the world could have been. To say that something exists in a possible world is just to say that, if the world were that way, then the thing would have existed. For example, even though unicorns don’t exist in the actual world, it seems at least possible that they could have. So we can say that unicorns exist in some possible world. On the other hand, a married bachelor does not exist in any possible world because the idea of a married bachelor is logically incoherent. It could not possibly exist.

This is not entirely accurate, so let's take a moment to clarify a few things.
 
Strictly speaking, possible worlds are not literal worlds per se. They are not alternate realities, they are not parallel dimensions, and they are not alien planets. Rather, a "possible world" is nothing but a collection of logically conjoined propositions with a self-consistent interpretation. For example,
 
"It is raining outside," and "I like pizza."
 
When I "imagine" a possible world, all I am doing is assigning a truth value to each of these propositions and then looking for contradictions. In this case, the world is said to be possible because the logical conjunction of those two propositions can be interpreted as true.
 
Now consider another hypothetical world:

"Jim is a bachelor" and "Jim is married."

This world is said to be impossible because conjunction of these two propositions has no self-consistent interpretation. It has nothing whatsoever to do with "the world" per se, but the basic rules of language. The standard English definitions for words like “married” and “bachelor” are logically exclusive from each other, which means the rules of binary logic do not allow for a true interpretation of any proposition expressing such a concept. Therefore, the idea of a married bachelor is incoherent and meaningless. Or, in the language of possible world semantics, we would say that “a married bachelor does not exist in any possible world.”
 
Notice how this only reinforces the idea that God’s existence has been asserted outright through pure definition. After all, if God is defined as a maximally great being in every possible world, then by definition there is no possible world without God. The very proposition itself---God does not exist---is therefore a logical contradiction. A thing that exists by definition cannot, by definition, not exist.
 
So once again, the ontological argument fails miserably under its own rules. It’s like trying to prove the existence of unicorns by simply defining the word "unicorn" as "a thing that totally exist.” And since unicorns are now officially things that exist, there is no possible world such that unicorns do not exist. 

Do you see the problem, here?

[1:40—1:50] So if it is possible that a maximally great being exists, then we can say that he exists in some possible world.

Except it's not possible for a maximally great being to exist. As we have already clearly established, nothing gets to exist by the mere virtue of its own definition. 
 
Incidentally, what exactly is this "if" nonsense? Remember that this entire argument began by straight-up defining God as a maximally great being in all possible worlds. This entire sentence is therefore logically and grammatically absurd. Just watch:
 
So if it is possible that a [being which exists in every possible world, including the actual world] exists, then we can say that [a being which exists in every possible world, including the actual world] exists in some possible world.
 
I am honestly baffled by this statement. What in the actual hell are you people even trying to say? I cannot tell if the makers of this video are being deliberately obtuse, or of they genuinely don't understand the implications of their own argument.

[1:50—2:05] But wait, a maximally great being would not really be maximally great if it existed in only some possible worlds. To be maximally great, it has to be all-powerful, all-knowing, and morally perfect in every possible world.

Yes. We know. That's literally what you defined "maximal greatness" to mean. All you did was reinforce every objection I’ve made up to this point. So unless you honestly would have us believe that pure, unfettered definition has the magical power to influence reality, then this argument has long-since failed.
 
But while we're on the subject, where exactly is it etched in stone that existence in every possible world is somehow "greater" than not existing in them? Are apologists really so childish as to think that greatness is determined entirely by numerical magnitude? For example, consider a morbidly obese man who weighs 450 lbs. Would it really be "greater" of him to weigh 460? Just because some number happens to be larger, that doesn't automatically make it a "greater" thing to possess.
 
Think of it this way. Imagine a possible world where Nazis have taken over the planet Earth. The bad guys have officially won, and they do nothing but oppress humanity for millions of years until finally all going extinct. Is that really such a “great” place for a morally perfect and all-powerful God to exist in? Just sitting there doing nothing while evil rules the world without any interference?
 
Which brings us to yet another fundamental problem with the ontological argument: The idea that "greatness" is some kind of objectively verifiable property of things. This video would actually have you believe that, in principle, scientists could hypothetically invent a device that empirically quantifies the supposed greatness of both material and immaterial objects. That's just nonsense! Greatness is not an objective thing to be measured or quantified. Greatness is what philosophers call a value judgement. That is to say, while it may be your sincere opinion that power, knowledge, and existence are “great” things to possess, other people are not necessarily obligated to share that assessment. All it means is that you personally consider certain traits as desirable to possess. It's a profoundly basic concept known as the fact/opinion distinction, and even children understand how it works.
 
But it gets worse than that! Even if we're feeling generous and decide to arbitrarily impose a standard by which to measure greatness, we still end up with all kinds of weird logical absurdities. For example, suppose I can lift 100 lbs of weight over my head, but my friend Carl can lift 200 lbs. Naturally, we might feel inclined to say that Carl has “greater strength” than myself. Indeed, that relation would indeed be objectively verifiable. That's fine, but remember that God is defined outright as a maximally great being. Therefore, God must, by definition, possess the power to lift the maximum weight possible. Except this is clearly a meaningless thing to say, because strength is not a bounded variable. You tell me how many pounds of God can lift, and I will tell you about my Super God who can lift just one more. It is therefore not logically possible for any being to possess maximally great strength because there is no such thing as a maximally great number!
 
That may sound like a philosophical nit-pick, but just be patient. The makers of this video are actually going to use that exact same argument to against a parody being of maximal greatness. Both William Lane Craig and his video production team therefore know, with conscious malicious forethought, that this is a deal-breaker for their own argument.

[2:05—2:25] So think about it. If a maximally great being exists in any possible world, then it exists in every possible world. And if it exists in every possible world, then it exists in the actual world. That is, a maximally great being actually exists.

Okay, let’s think about it. If a maximally great being does not exist in some possible world, then it exists in no possible world. And if exists in no possible world, then it does not exist in the actual world. That is, a maximally great being actually does not exist. 
 
Remember that is your own argument, guys. You're the ones imposing the all-or-nothing condition on your God’s possibility. Therefore, if it is even possible that God does not exist, then God cannot exist. Are you sure you want to go down this road?

[2:25—2:32] Thus, the atheist has to maintain not simply that God does not exist, but that it is impossible that God exists.

Okay. Done. It is impossible for God to exist. As we already demonstrated earlier on, necessary existence is not a logical possibility. 
 
But it gets even worse than that! Remember that I have no obligation whatsoever to show that it is "impossible" for God to exist. Rather, I only have to show that it is possible for God to not exist. Again, the apologists are the ones who imposed this all-or-nothing attitude onto their God. So if it is even possible that He doesn't exist, then it is necessary that He doesn't exist. Let us therefore cut to the chase and settle this right now:
 
Imagine a possible world such that God does not exist.
 
Ask yourself. Was that sentence meaningful to you? Was it comprehensible and self-consistent? Or did I just barf up an incoherent string of meaningless, self-contradictory nonsense?
 
This is yet another reason why necessary existence is absolutely not a coherent concept. You tell me about the all supposedly amazing properties of God, and I will immediately imagine a logically possible world without Him in it. And since that contradicts the idea of existing in every possible world, we have an instant proof by demonstration and deduction that such a God cannot exist.

So there you have it. It is impossible for God to exist. I have officially met the very burden of proof which you just demanded. Now can we please stop wasting people’s time with this nonsense?
 
I apologize if my tone sounds harsh, but philosophers have been pointing this stuff out for centuries. This isn't exactly rocket science, either, which makes it difficult to understand what possible motivations could drive the people at Reasonable Faith. Are they really so incompetent at basic philosophy that they don’t even understand their own argument? Or are they just that cynical in their exploitation of the naïve credulity of their audience? I honestly can’t tell.

[2:32—2:41] Here is a summary of the ontological argument. Steps 2-6 are straightforward and largely uncontroversial.


This is yet another complete fabrication of the collective imaginations at Reasonable Faith. Premise #3 is actually quite controversial, and obviously so. I mean, just look at: If God exists in some possible world, then God exists in all of them? In what logical universe does that even begin to make sense? It’s like trying to say that if Bill owns a home in California, then Bill owns a home in every state in America. It's another classic fallacy known as affirming the consequent, and any first-year philosophy student can see it.

Remember that the key to the ontological argument is the premise that God exists in every possible world. Yet for some very bizarre reason, the formal version of it always leaves this little premise out. Thus, a far more appropriate parody would look something like this:
  1. Bill owns a home in every state in America.
  2. Bill owns a home in California. 
  3. If Bill owns a home in California, then Bill owns a home in every state in America.
  4. If Bill owns a home in every state in America, then Bill owns a home in Maine. 
  5. Therefore, Bill owns a home in Maine. 
That's the real argument being made here. Silly, isn't it?
 
[2:41—2:50] But what about point #1? Clearly, if it can be shown that the idea of a God is logically incoherent, then the argument fails.
 
Okay. Done. The idea of God has definitely been shown to be logically incoherent. I gave you at least five reasons off the top of my head, and I'm sure philosophers could probably give you a few dozen more if they put their minds to it.
 
[2:50—3:02] But is the idea of a maximally great being absurd? Like a married bachelor, or a square circle, or the smell of blue? This doesn’t seem to be the case. 

Seriously? It doesn’t “seem” to be the case to you? Is that really how logic works in the world of Christian philosophy? As in, let's just define God outright as existing, and nobody could possibly have any reason to object to that?

[3:02—3:12] The notion of an all-powerful, all-knowing, and perfectly morally being that exists in every possible world seems to be a perfectly coherent idea.

Seriously? Again? It just “seems” to be coherent to you? You see nothing wrong with existence as a matter of pure definition? That's your big argument?

[3:12—3:33] But couldn’t we parody this argument and make it work for everything? Why not say, “It is logically possible that a maximally great pizza exists, therefore, a maximally great pizza does exist.” However, the idea of a maximally great pizza is not like the idea of a maximally great being.

And, as if circular logic wasn’t bad enough, we now get to watch as a PhD philosopher of religion plows headlong into the fallacy of special pleading. Maximally great pizzas are totally not like maximally great beings, even though both of them were asserted outright via the same mechanism of rote definition..

[3:33—3:54] In the first place, there aren’t intrinsic maximal values that make pizzas great. There could always be one more pepperoni to increase its greatness. It’s not even obvious what properties make a pizza great; thin crust or thick crust? Extra cheese? Anchovies? Its relative to the taste of the consumer.

And as if special pleading wasn't enough, we now get to watch this video plow even further into yet another classic logical fallacy known as kettle logic---an argument that, once accepted, only serves as a counter-argument against your own position. Reasonable Faith has just admitted openly that greatness is not some objectively measurable thing. It’s a value judgement! They even further undermine themselves by admitting to the problem of unbounded variables---as in, there could always be “one more” pepperoni! These are the exact same arguments that I just provided against the idea of a maximally great being, which means Reasonable Faith is only debunking themselves.
 
This is exactly how we know that the makers of this video are nothing but out-and-out liars. You cannot possibly expect me to believe that someone would go through all that trouble explaining maximal greatness and necessary existence, despite knowing full-well that these ideas are obviously incoherent in every other context.

[3:54—4:08] In the second place, a maximally great pizza would have to exist in every logically possible world. But that would mean that it couldn’t be eaten. So, it wouldn’t really be a pizza, because a pizza is something you can eat.

Not unless it’s a self-regenerating pizza that instantly replenishes itself every time you take a slice. That would be pretty "great," don’t you think? It certainly "seems to be the case" to me.
 
But hey, if that’s how you want to play it, then fine. Meet Eric, the God-Eating Penguin [5]. By definition, Eric is a maximally great penguin that eats God in every possible world. Therefore, if God exists, then Eric would have no choice but to eat Him. Therefore, if Reasonable Faith wants to prove God's existence, then they must first dis-prove the existence of Eric---except the moment you do that, the very same logic applies equally well to God, and the argument fails again.

[4:08—4:40] The idea of a maximally great pizza turns out not to be a coherent idea. The idea of God, on the other hand, is an intuitively coherent idea. Therefore, His existence is a possibility. And the ontological argument shows that, if God possible exists, then God actually exists. 

And there you have it, folks. The modal ontological argument in a nutshell. God exists in every possible world because Christian philosophers say so. Not only does it beg the question by outright assuming its own conclusion, but it actually confuses subjective preferences with objectively verifiable properties. It then attempts to maximize unbounded variables, it fails to grasp its own logical implications, it justifies itself through pure, touchy-feelies, it fallaciously affirms the consequent, it neglects essential premises of its own argument, it commits special pleading, and it outright debunks itself through its own kettle logic. Philosophers have documented all of these problems, and more, over the last hundred years or more, yet proponents still have the colossal arrogance to present this thing as some kind of monumental achievement in Christian philosophy.
 
I genuinely apologize if my tone is feels off-putting, but how else am I supposed to react when presented with such baffling nonsense? This isn't just a bad argument. It's an absolute dumpster fire. If I were a Christian, I would be enraged by this. Decades of research into the very best arguments of mainstream Christian philosophy, and this is what they come up with? God exists because… it would be… like… totally awesome if He did? Are apologists really that incompetent? Or do they have so little regard for your intellectual capacity that they actually expect you to feel compelled by this nonsense?

You tell me…

Thank you for reading.

References:

  1. David Bourget and David Chalmers, "The 2020 PhilPapers Survey" [link]
  2. "Ontological Arguments," The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy [link]---There is fairly widespread consensus, even amongst theists, that no known ontological arguments for the existence of God are persuasive.
  3. "It seems fair to say that analytic philosophers, in general, even analytic philosophers who are theists, have largely ignored Hartshorne’s philosophy."---Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  4. Nicholas P. Wolterstorff & Alvin Plantinga, "Faith and Rationality: Reason and Belief in God," 1983  [link]
  5. See The Problem of Omnipotence
  6. Eric the God Eating Penguin